Skip to content →

Category: number theory

Langlands versus Connes

This is a belated response to a Math-Overflow exchange between Thomas Riepe and Chandan Singh Dalawat asking for a possible connection between Connes’ noncommutative geometry approach to the Riemann hypothesis and the Langlands program.

Here’s the punchline : a large chunk of the Connes-Marcolli book Noncommutative Geometry, Quantum Fields and Motives can be read as an exploration of the noncommutative boundary to the Langlands program (at least for GL1 and GL2 over the rationals Q).

Recall that Langlands for GL1 over the rationals is the correspondence, given by the Artin reciprocity law, between on the one hand the abelianized absolute Galois group

Gal(Q/Q)ab=Gal(Q(μ)/Q)Z^

and on the other hand the connected components of the idele classes

AQ/Q=R+×Z^

The locally compact Abelian group of idele classes can be viewed as the nice locus of the horrible quotient space of adele classes AQ/Q. There is a well-defined map

AQ/QR+(x,x2,x3,)|x||xp|p

from the subset AQ consisting of adeles of which almost all terms belong to Zp. The inverse image of this map over R+ are precisely the idele classes AQ/Q. In this way one can view the adele classes as a closure, or ‘compactification’, of the idele classes.

This is somewhat reminiscent of extending the nice action of the modular group on the upper-half plane to its badly behaved action on the boundary as in the Manin-Marcolli cave post.

The topological properties of the fiber over zero, and indeed of the total space of adele classes, are horrible in the sense that the discrete group Q acts ergodically on it, due to the irrationality of log(p1)/log(p2) for primes pi. All this is explained well (in the semi-local case, that is using AQ above) in the Connes-Marcolli book (section 2.7).

In much the same spirit as non-free actions of reductive groups on algebraic varieties are best handled using stacks, such ergodic actions are best handled by the tools of noncommutative geometry. That is, one tries to get at the geometry of AQ/Q by studying an associated non-commutative algebra, the skew-ring extension of the group-ring of the adeles by the action of Q on it. This algebra is known to be Morita equivalent to the Bost-Connes algebra which is the algebra featuring in Connes’ approach to the Riemann hypothesis.

It shouldn’t thus come as a major surprise that one is able to recover the other side of the Langlands correspondence, that is the Galois group Gal(Q(μ)/Q), from the Bost-Connes algebra as the symmetries of certain states.

In a similar vein one can read the Connes-Marcolli GL2-system (section 3.7 of their book) as an exploration of the noncommutative closure of the Langlands-space GL2(AQ)/GL2(Q).

At the moment I’m running a master-seminar noncommutative geometry trying to explain this connection in detail. But, we’re still in the early phases, struggling with the topology of ideles and adeles, reciprocity laws, L-functions and the lot. Still, if someone is interested I might attempt to post some lecture notes here.

Comments closed

Lambda-rings for formula-phobics

In 1956, Alexander Grothendieck (middle) introduced λ-rings in an algebraic-geometric context to be commutative rings A equipped with a bunch of operations λi (for all numbers iN+) satisfying a list of rather obscure identities. From the easier ones, such as

λ0(x)=1,λ1(x)=x,λn(x+y)=iλi(x)λni(y)

to those expressing λn(x.y) and λm(λn(x)) via specific universal polynomials. An attempt to capture the essence of λ-rings without formulas?

Lenstra’s elegant construction of the 1-power series rings  (Λ(A),,) requires only one identity to remember

 (1at)1(1bt)1=(1abt)1.

Still, one can use it to show the existence of ringmorphisms γn : Λ(A)A, for all numbers nN+. Consider the formal ‘logarithmic derivative’

γ=tu(t)u(t)=i=1γi(u(t))ti : Λ(A)A[[t]]

where u(t) is the usual formal derivative of a power series. As this derivative satisfies the chain rule, we have

γ(u(t)v(t))=t(u(t)v(t))u(t)v(t)=t(u(t)v(t)+u(t)v(t)u(t)v(t))=tu(t)u(t)+tv(t)v(t)=γ(u(t))+γ(v(t))

and so all the maps γn : Λ(A)A are additive. To show that they are also multiplicative, it suffices by functoriality to verify this on the special 1-series  (1at)1 for all aA. But,

γ((1at)1)=ta(1at)2(1at)=at(1at)=at+a2t2+a3t3+

That is, γn((1at)1)=an and Lenstra’s identity implies that γn is indeed multiplicative! A first attempt :

hassle-free definition 1 : a commutative ring A is a λ-ring if and only if there is a ringmorphism sA : AΛ(A) splitting γ1, that is, such that γ1sA=idA.

In particular, a λ-ring comes equipped with a multiplicative set of ring-endomorphisms sn=γnsA : AA satisfying smsm=smn. One can then define a λ-ringmorphism to be a ringmorphism commuting with these endo-morphisms.

The motivation being that λ-rings are known to form a subcategory of commutative rings for which the 1-power series functor is the right adjoint to the functor forgetting the λ-structure. In particular, if A is a λ-ring, we have a ringmorphism AΛ(A) corresponding to the identity morphism.

But then, what is the connection to the usual one involving all the operations λi? Well, one ought to recover those from sA(a)=(1λ1(a)t+λ2(a)t2λ3(a)t3+)1.

For sA to be a ringmorphism will require identities among the λi. I hope an expert will correct me on this one, but I’d guess we won’t yet obtain all identities required. By the very definition of an adjoint we must have that sA is a morphism of λ-rings, and, this would require defining a λ-ring structure on Λ(A), that is a ringmorphism sAH : Λ(A)Λ(Λ(A)), the so called Artin-Hasse exponential, to which I’d like to return later.

For now, we can define a multiplicative set of ring-endomorphisms fn : Λ(A)Λ(A) from requiring that fn((1at)1)=(1ant)1 for all aA. Another try?

hassle-free definition 2 : A is a λ-ring if and only if there is splitting sA to γ1 satisfying the compatibility relations fnsA=sAsn.

But even then, checking that a map sA : AΛ(A) is a ringmorphism is as hard as verifying the lists of identities among the λi. Fortunately, we get such a ringmorphism for free in the important case when A is of ‘characteristic zero’, that is, has no additive torsion. Then, a ringmorphism AΛ(A) exists whenever we have a multiplicative set of ring endomorphisms Fn : AA for all nN+ such that for every prime number p the morphism Fp is a lift of the Frobenius, that is, Fp(a)ap+pA.

Perhaps this captures the essence of λ-rings best (without the risk of getting an headache) : in characteristic zero, they are the (commutative) rings having a multiplicative set of endomorphisms, generated by lifts of the Frobenius maps.

Comments closed

Seating the first few thousand Knights

The Knight-seating problems asks for a consistent placing of n-th Knight at an odd root of unity, compatible with the two different realizations of the algebraic closure of the field with two elements.
The first identifies the multiplicative group of its non-zero elements with the group of all odd complex roots of unity, under complex multiplication. The second uses Conway’s ‘simplicity rules’ to define an addition and multiplication on the set of all ordinal numbers.

The odd Knights of the round table-problem asks for a specific one-to-one correspondence between two realizations of ‘the’ algebraic closure F2 of the field of two elements.

The first identifies the multiplicative group of its non-zero elements with the group of all odd complex roots of unity, under complex multiplication. The addition on F2 is then recovered by inducing an involution on the odd roots, pairing the one corresponding to x to the one corresponding to x+1.

The second uses Conway’s ‘simplicity rules’ to define an addition and multiplication on the set of all ordinal numbers. Conway proves in ONAG that this becomes an algebraically closed field of characteristic two and that F2 is the subfield of all ordinals smaller than ωωω. The finite ordinals (the natural numbers) form the quadratic closure of F2.

On the natural numbers the Conway-addition is binary addition without carrying and Conway-multiplication is defined by the properties that two different Fermat-powers N=22i multiply as they do in the natural numbers, and, Fermat-powers square to its sesquimultiple, that is N2=32N. Moreover, all natural numbers smaller than N=22i form a finite field F22i. Using distributivity, one can write down a multiplication table for all 2-powers.



The Knight-seating problems asks for a consistent placing of n-th Knight Kn at an odd root of unity, compatible with the two different realizations of F2. Last time, we were able to place the first 15 Knights as below, and asked where you would seat K16



K4 was placed at e2πi/15 as 4 was the smallest number generating the ‘Fermat’-field F222 (with multiplicative group of order 15) subject to the compatibility relation with the generator 2 of the smaller Fermat-field F2 (with group of order 15) that 45=2.

To include the next Fermat-field F223 (with multiplicative group of order 255) consistently, we need to find the smallest number n generating the multiplicative group and satisfying the compatibility condition n17=4. Let’s first concentrate on finding the smallest generator : as 2 is a generator for 1st Fermat-field F221 and 4 a generator for the 2-nd Fermat-field F222 a natural conjecture might be that 16 is a generator for the 3-rd Fermat-field F223 and, more generally, that 22i would be a generator for the next field F22i+1.

However, an “exercise” in the 1978-paper by Hendrik Lenstra Nim multiplication asks : “Prove that 22i is a primitive root in the field F22i+1 if and only if i=0 or 1.”

I’ve struggled with several of the ‘exercises’ in Lenstra’s paper to the extend I feared Alzheimer was setting in, only to find out, after taking pen and paper and spending a considerable amount of time calculating, that they are indeed merely exercises, when looked at properly… (Spoiler-warning : stop reading now if you want to go through this exercise yourself).

In the picture above I’ve added in red the number x(x+1)=x2+1 to each of the involutions. Clearly, for each pair these numbers are all distinct and we see that for the indicated pairing they make up all numbers strictly less than 8.

By Conway’s simplicity rules (or by checking) the pair (16,17) gives the number 8. In other words, the equation
x2+x+8 is an irreducible polynomial over F16 having as its roots in F256 the numbers 16 and 17. But then, 16 and 17 are conjugated under the Galois-involution (the Frobenius yy16). That is, we have 1616=17 and 1716=16 and hence 1617=8. Now, use the multiplication table in F16 given in the previous post (or compute!) to see that 8 is of order 5 (and NOT a generator). As a consequence, the multiplicative order of 16 is 5×17=85 and so 16 cannot be a generator in F256.
For general i one uses the fact that 22i and 22i+1 are the roots of the polynomial x2+x+j<i22j over F22i and argues as before.

Right, but then what is the minimal generator satisfying n17=4? By computing we see that the pairings of all numbers in the range 16…31 give us all numbers in the range 8…15 and by the above argument this implies that the 17-th powers of all numbers smaller than 32 must be different from 4. But then, the smallest candidate is 32 and one verifies that indeed 3217=4 (use the multiplication table given before).

Hence, we must place Knight K32 at root e2πi/255 and place the other Knights prior to the 256-th at the corresponding power of 32. I forgot the argument I used to find-by-hand the requested place for Knight 16, but one can verify that 32171=16 so we seat K16 at root e342πi/255.

But what about Knight K256? Well, by this time I was quite good at squaring and binary representations of integers, but also rather tired, and decided to leave that task to the computer.

If we denote Nim-addition and multiplication by and , then Conway’s simplicity results in ONAG establish a field-isomorphism between  (N,,) and the field F2(x0,x1,x2,) where the xi satisfy the Artin-Schreier equations

xi2+xi+j<ixj=0

and the i-th Fermat-field F22i corresponds to F2(x0,x1,,xi1). The correspondence between numbers and elements from these fields is given by taking xi22i. But then, wecan write every 2-power as a product of the xi and use the binary representation of numbers to perform all Nim-calculations with numbers in these fields.

Therefore, a quick and dirty way (and by no means the most efficient) to do Nim-calculations in the next Fermat-field consisting of all numbers smaller than 65536, is to use sage and set up the field F2(x0,x1,x2,x3) by

R.< x,y,z,t > =GF(2)[]
S.< a,b,c,d >=R.quotient((x^2+x+1,y^2+y+x,z^2+z+x*y,t^2+t+x*y*z))

To find the smallest number generating the multiplicative group and satisfying the additional compatibility condition n257=32 we have to find the smallest binary number i1i2i16 (larger than 255) satisfying

(i1*a*b*c*t+i2*b*c*t+i3*a*c*t+i4*c*t+i5*a*b*t+i6*b*t+
i7*a*t+i8*t+i9*a*b*c+i10*b*c+i11*a*c+i12*c+i13*a*b+
i14*b+i15*a+i16)^257=a*c

It takes a 2.4GHz 2Gb-RAM MacBook not that long to decide that the requested generator is 1051 (killing another optimistic conjecture that these generators might be 2-powers). So, we seat Knight
K1051 at root e2πi/65535 and can then arrange seatings for all Knight queued up until we reach the 65536-th! In particular, the first Knight we couldn’t place before, that is Knight K256, will be seated at root e65826πi/65535.

If you’re lucky enough to own a computer with more RAM, or have the patience to make the search more efficient and get the seating arrangement for the next Fermat-field, please drop a comment.

I’ll leave you with another Lenstra-exercise which shouldn’t be too difficult for you to solve now : “Prove that x3=22i has three solutions in N for each i2.”

Comments closed